Vol , Issue Date of Publication: January 01, 2002

Views
, PDF Downloads:

FROM OTHER JOURNALS


Trade and our health

This editorial notes that while developing countries’ negotiations with the World Trade Organization on trade related aspects of intellectual property rights will be important for their access to essential drugs for life threatening diseases, the WTO’s agreements also affect national policies on a range of other health-related issues.

“Some of the proposals under negotiation regarding GATT indicate that developing countries will be asked to open up health service markets to foreign competition… experience in middle income countries indicates that foreign competition in health service markets tends to worsen equity in financing and reduce access to care for the poor.”

Health care will be affected even without a liberalisation of trade in health services, as the WTO discusses other services such as health insurance. As the US and the European Union demand access to the insurance market in countries like India, the experience of private insurance in Latin America teaches a lesson on how these companies operate, selecting the healthiest people and dumping high-cost patients on to the public sector.

“After trade related aspects of intellectual property rights and access to drugs, the next major health issue on the agenda of the World Trade Organization may well arise in the course of negotiations on trade in services. Health professionals need to work with trade officials to minimise the risks to health equity from liberalisation of services trade, and ensure that any resulting economic gains in health related service sectors generate tangible public health benefits.

Lipson Debra J. The World Trade Organization’s health agenda Opening up the health services markets may worsen health equity for the poor. Editorial. BMJ 2001;323:1139-1140.

In favour of sex selection

In recent months, a series of articles have appeared in ethics journals in the West, discussing the ethics of sex selection. These essays are particularly important for those following current developments in India on sex selective abortion and other sex selection techniques. David McCarthy argues that that medically assisted sex selection for non-medical reasons ought to be legal: it cannot do harm to individual children, there is no evidence that it is affecting the sex ratio of western societies. Sex selection is one form of reproductive autonomy, giving parents the right to choose the child of a particular sex.

McCarthy David. Why sex selection should be legal J Med Ethics 2001; 27:302-307.

It’s immoral but not necessarily illegal

J M Johnston examines the law and practice on sex selective abortion in New Zealand, and also examines the various arguments for and against the practice. Johnston suggests that even if sex selective abortion is not based on son preference – with its social consequences – its is morally wrong becase it encourages discrimination based on sex. “…sex is not a morally appropriate differentiating factor and allowing sex selective abortions will mean allowing abortions for trivial and unjustifiably discriminatory reasons, thus undermining the serious and strong reasons most women have for seeking the procedure.” Interestingly, Johnston concludes that while it is immoral, sex selective abortion must be tolerated wherever abortion is available on demand.

Johnston JM. Are sex-selective abortions wrong? New Zealand Bioethics Journal. 2001 February: 9-16.

Does appealing to ethics work?

This collection of three essays discusses pharmaceutical companies’ responsibilities to provide drugs in poor countries at an affordable price. David Resnick acknowledges the companies’ responsibilities but argues that they are not absolute. They “may be balanced against other obligations and commitments”. A company may also look at the business environment and the scope for a profit. Developing country governments must respect international trade agreements, and can work in cooperation with industry (rather than confront it) to encourage it to act responsibly. Dan W Brock challenges the arguments made by Resnick that companies have a social responsibility. Separately, he suggests that even if such a social responsibility were acknowledged, this would not go far towards meeting the drug needs of the developing world, given that pharmaceutical companies’ first responsibility is to their stock-holders. The vast income inequalities between rich and poor countries will force the latter to ignore patents if they are to provide their people with essential drugs. In other words, poor countries would do better if they confronted pharmaceutical companies, instead of appealed to their social responsibilities. Norman Daniels also questions Resnick’s appeal to social responsibilites, proposing instead that the solution is to regulate pharmaceutical companies, both internationally and domestically.

Resnick D. Developing drugs for the developing world: an economic, legal, moral and political dilemma. Developing World Bioethics 2001; 1: 11-32. Brock Dan W. Some questions about the moral responsibilities of drug companies in developing countries. Developing World Bioethics 2001; 1: 33-37. Daniels Norman. Social responsibility and global pharmaceutical companies. Developing World Bioethics 2001; 1: 38-41.

Why dangerous drugs are not banned

When a very profitable drug is banned abroad for its adverse effects, interest groups in India resist similar action here. This editorial illustrates the point with reference to the drug cisapride. It refers to a report in the Indian Drug Review on a meeting questioning the value of a ban on cisapride in India. The meeting argued that the drug is cheap and cardiac adverse affects due to its use have not been reported in this country – even while admitting that we have no system of adverse drug reporting. “What the ‘meeting of the minds’ wants is simply this: Cisapride has a market. The manufacturers cannot simply sacrifice it for the safety of the consumers. So ‘an Indian system of adverse drug reactions should be evolved’. This may take years or even decades. The manufacturers will have ample time to make their proits, never mind what happens to the hapless consumers.”

Editorial. Why not engage others to homework while we go on eating the pie and killing people? BODHI 2000; 37: 129.

Eugenic abortion

This writer re-examines the moral status of abortion in the context of current genetic research which is likely to lead to a growth prenatal genetic testing. He concludes that “secular philosophy should ultimately admit that the moral status of the fetus is uncertain, and this uncertainty itself makes abortion morally problematic. While this does not imply that abortion is always morally wrong or that it should be legally prohibited, it does recommend a [moral] presumption in favor of preserving fetal life except in special circumstances. A relevant worry is that the rise of eugenic abortion gives new force to slippery slope arguments that we will be led down a path to a situation where more fetuses are terminated for relatively trivial reasons and that this will promote other bad social consequences. This might justify legislative discouragement of certain genetic interventions.”

Selgelid Michael J. Eugenic abortion, moral uncertainty and social consequences. Monash Bioethics Review 2001; 20: 26-42.

Genetic counselling

In a society where women get blamed for infertility, for the sex of the child, or for any disability, medical professionals must be thoughtful while disclosing genetic disorders to the family. Women have faced discrimination from their husbands and in-laws because of a genetic disorder in their children. The writers discuss three cases which lead them to reassess the use of genetic counseling in India, particularly in relation to the policy of disclosure of women’s carrier status. They suggest that the problem will become more serious with the growth of genetic centres in the country, and the shortage of professionally trained genetics counselors. Information provided during genetic counseling should not lead the woman to feel guilty, or the family members to blame her. The authors call for the development of ethical guidelines for genetic counseling, which are appropriate for the Indian situation.

Phadke Shubha R, Agarwal SS. Adverse effects of genetic counseling on women carriers of disease: the Indian perspective. Natnl Med J India 2001; 47-49.
About the Authors
Editorial Team ()
Help IJME keep its content free. You can support us from as little as Rs. 500 Make a Donation