Vol , Issue Date of Publication: August 16, 2017
DOI: https://doi.org/10.20529/IJME.2017.076

Views
, PDF Downloads:

COMMENTS

Placing the “radar” under the radar: ethics of public health surveillance

Vijayaprasad Gopichandran

Published online: August 16, 2017

DOI: https://doi.org/10.20529/IJME.2017.076


Abstract

Public health surveillance (PHS) is an essential public health activity, which entails collecting data on diseases and disease-related states in a timely manner to aid in international health regulations and in local health planning. Opinions differ sharply on whether it is a research or non-research activity. In recent years, most low- and middle-income countries (LMICs) have been establishing their own PHS systems, with or without support from external donors, to comply with the stipulations of international health regulations. With the expansion of the scope and role of PHS in ensuring the health security of countries, it is important to understand the ethical principles of PHS and the specific ethical issues involved in it, as well as the need for ethical oversight of PHS. This paper deals with these aspects of PHS, and highlights the need for specific ethical guidance and oversight mechanisms in LMICs that are setting up their own PHS systems.

Introduction

Public health surveillance (PHS), also referred to as the “radar” of public health, can be defined as the ongoing, systematic collection, collation, analysis, interpretation and dissemination of health-related data in a timely manner to those who need to know, so as to effectively plan, implement and evaluate public health activities (1). The National Institute of Communicable Diseases, South Africa defines it as “continuous analysis, interpretation and feedback of systematically collected data, generally using methods distinguished by their practicability, uniformity and rapidity” (2). According to an older definition, PHS is “a system of close observation of all aspects of the occurrence and distribution of a given disease through the systematic collection, tabulation, analysis and dissemination of all relevant data pertaining to that disease” (3). This activity is essential for the proper planning and delivery of public health interventions. Originally, the term PHS was used to refer to infectious disease surveillance, but now it encompasses a wide array of targets that are under scrutiny. These are chronic diseases, chronic disease risk factors, and environmental exposures. Several modalities of surveillance of health-related states and events have been in use. The most common and time-tested modality is the reporting of diseases by health providers, health facilities and laboratories. Of late, non-surveillance data are being used for PHS. Vital registrations, health information systems, disease registries, demographic and health survey data, law enforcement records, etc. are all used as sources of data for PHS (4, 5, 6). The social media and Internet-based data are also used for PHS (7). Given this expansion of the role and scope of PHS in recent years, the ethical considerations in the practice of PHS are now a matter of global concern. Several important ethical issues are involved in the practice of PHS. These are as follows.

Ethical imperative to perform PHS

Conducting PHS is necessary to ensure local and global health security. Health security has been defined in several ways. Health security includes protection against threats such as poverty, hunger, disease, pandemics and bio-terrorism; the provision of medical aid and humanitarian assistance during conflict; and the involvement of military and political interests to prevent the cross-border spread of diseases (8). The International Health Regulations, which were modified in 2005 and came into force in 2007, have been ratified by 196 countries. They aim to “prevent, protect against, control and provide a public health response to the international spread of disease” (9). The recent Ebola epidemic in West Africa created awareness of the collective threat to health security and more importantly, of the threat to the health security of each individual in these countries. The epidemic revealed the fragile nature of international boundaries when it comes to global health threats. It also exposed weaknesses in the PHS mechanisms in vulnerable countries. The most vulnerable countries in terms of the capacity to perform PHS face the greatest threat to global health security and hence, it is a moral imperative to support the establishment of good surveillance systems in these countries through international cooperation (10). Non-communicable diseases (NCDs) place a huge burden on the low- and middle-income countries (LMICs). A strong PHS system would protect the vulnerable countries from NCDs too (11). A strong PHS is not only important in the global context, but is also very helpful in checking the local spread of diseases. It provides data that are useful for the effective planning of the delivery of health services. PHS provides data on the magnitude of specific health problems in the local area, portrays the natural history of the disease, shows the distribution and spread of the illness, provides information on the most effective control measures that can be taken and indicates the resources required to implement these. It thus facilitates the effective planning of public health interventions in the local area (12). There are several important ethical principles which govern and direct PHS.

Ethical principles involved in PHS

As with any public health activity, the key ethical principle underlying PHS is the common good. The concept of common good extends beyond the provision of good to the individuals in the community. It includes the good that accrues to the community as a whole, including even those who do not participate in PHS and those who are not yet born into the community (13, 14, 15). Those who are part of the community may not be able to shun the benefits even if they fail to participate in PHS.

The principle of equity is integral to PHS, as it is the most underdeveloped areas with poor PHS capacity that face the greatest threats to health security, besides posing the greatest challenge to the global spread of disease. This was evident from the recent Ebola epidemic in West Africa, where countries with a poor PHS capacity not only suffered the brunt of the disease, but also posed a serious global threat (10). Considerations of equity demand that PHS include marginalised and vulnerable populations as much as mainstream populations. The benefits and burdens of PHS should be distributed equitably between the well off and the vulnerable. Often, high-income countries support the establishment of PHS in LMICs, targeting specific diseases that are a threat to the high-income countries. This places an ethical burden of compromising on privacy and confidentiality on the low- and middle-income regions that is disproportionate to the benefits which accrue mainly to the high-income regions. An example of this kind of inequitable surveillance plan is the establishment of surveillance of disease pathogens in the LMICs by the USA under the Global Pathogen Surveillance Act. The USA offers training, capacity-building and the establishment of high-technology laboratories in these countries in exchange for surveillance of pathogens that are of research and academic interest in the USA (16). This type of inequity should be addressed and the benefits and burdens balanced (14, 17).

Individual autonomy, privacy and confidentiality have a secondary role among the ethical principles of PHS because the effectiveness of a surveillance activity will be compromised if all members of the community are not included. However, no explanation based on the common good can justify disproportionate violations of the respect due to an individual as a member of the community. The principles of proportionality and public justification of the PHS are important (15, 18). Are the burdens of intrusion into the individual’s privacy by accessing his/her disease-related information proportional to the common good accrued to the community? Sometimes, PHS involves the collection of people’s personal identifying information, such as their names and contact details, to ensure that they are treated, trace their contacts to prevent the spread of infection and institute control measures in the neighbourhood. In the case of certain stigmatising diseases, such as leprosy, tuberculosis and HIV/AIDS, it is important to assess whether such name-based disease surveillance and consequent stigmatisation of the patient, is proportional to the benefits of having such data and reporting it. In such stigmatising conditions, anonymous reporting or reporting stripped of identifying information may be more proportional to the benefits. In some settings, unlinked anonymous testing (UAT) has been suggested for HIV as a method to avoid selection bias. The testing is not based on “informed consent”, there is no breach of confidentiality and at the same time, effective PHS data may be collected. However, UAT is associated with an ethical burden, which is that the results of the test can never be traced back to the patient and declared (19). Such burdens of PHS should be publicly justifiable and acceptable to the community.

In relation to the community’s acceptance of such infringements of individual privacy emerges the principle of community engagement. Community engagement is the process of working collaboratively with and for groups of people who are connected by geographical proximity, special interests or similar health-related factors that affect the health of the community (20). Community engagement is essential for the ethical delivery of PHS since it entails better protection of the community’s interest, creating and sharing benefits for the community, establishing the legitimacy of the surveillance effort, and encouraging the sharing of responsibility for benefits and risks (21).

Accountability is another important ethical principle of PHS. It is defined as answerability for interventions, along with sanctions for poor performance (22). Proper accountability is ensured by setting up monitoring and evaluation systems and good governance systems for PHS. Accountability to the community in the matter of health security can be achieved by having proper standard operating procedures, effective quality assurance mechanisms, incentives and sanctions to regulate the performance of the surveillance (22). In many LMICs, PHS is implemented in a programme mode, with the support of an external donor. In such situations, the sustainability of the PHS is of prime importance. Sustained PHS leads to long-term benefits, covers the latency period between the introduction of PHS and the time by which it begins to have favourable effects on populations, and promotes and maintains the trust of the community in the activity (23). Several important ethical issues that are specific to PHS emerge from these central principles.

Specific ethical issues in PHS

Certain ethical issues arise when setting up a PHS system for an area. These are how far it is responsive to the local health priorities; whether the human resources used are adequate and appropriate; and whether the system focuses on strengthening of the overall health system (unlike vertical surveillance programmes). The PHS system should be responsive to local health needs. LMICs such as India are facing a dual epidemiological burden of communicable as well as non-communicable diseases (24). Therefore, PHS systems should focus on both these aspects. The capacity of LMICs to actively monitor and perform surveillance of the risk factors for and outcomes of NCDs is poor, and with the changing epidemiology of NCDs in these countries, there is a need for PHS to be responsive to the situation (25). Malaria, tuberculosis and HIV/AIDS receive a lot of global attention, and there is a good amount of funding for research and capacity-building in these areas. This is because these are focal diseases in the Sustainable Development Goals agenda (26). However, there are neglected tropical diseases, such as dengue, leprosy, leptospirosis, cholera, hookworm, leishmaniasis, rabies, chikungunya, cysticercosis and hydatid cyst, in the LMICs that do not receive the same kind of attention. The local PHS systems should keep these in mind (27, 28). Apart from setting priorities for PHS, there is also a need to set up efficient systems in LMICs at a cost that is affordable.

The appropriate use of human resources for health is essential in this context. The PHS system may rely on hospital/health facility-based reporting, laboratory-based reporting, syndromic surveillance by field-level community health workers, media news surveillance or rumour surveillance. Human resources are essential for all these approaches. In India, syndromic surveillance driven by community health workers has been used in several vertical surveillance programmes. The existing Integrated Disease Surveillance Programme (IDSP), sponsored by the World Bank and established in 2006 (29), is also based on this approach. In this context, the issue of overburdening health workers should be borne in mind. Attempts to appropriately motivate the health workers involved in surveillance, such as with incentives, may be helpful in improving efficiency (17). Conflicts of interest may also arise as the health worker plays the dual role of delivering preventive health service and performing the syndromic surveillance. As a person delivering preventive care, he/she is supposed to ensure low rates of disease in the population. This conflicts with the role of being a surveillance reporter, who has to accurately report every person who has the disease.

A systems approach to PHS, rather than an approach based on a vertical programme, is likely to improve the performance of the public health system. It is well known that health systems are complex, adaptive systems, the components of which work in a non-linear and dynamic manner. There is mutual feedback and learning between the components, patterns emerge through interaction between them, and the behaviours of the system are often unpredictable (30). Therefore, the establishment of a PHS system may have synergistic and multiplicative beneficial effects on the overall health system. For example, training health workers to effectively capture illness by syndromic reporting may sensitise them to the need to intensify preventive measures and strengthen the public health interventions. It may also make them stronger health advocates. This is a typical effect of one component of the system feeding into and enhancing the other.

In the context of PHS, we come across another unique set of ethical issues, ie infringements into the privacy and confidentiality of community members, potential use of healthcare service data for PHS purposes, dissemination and sharing of PHS data, and establishment of appropriate standards of care for those diagnosed through surveillance. In epidemiological and public health activities like PHS, especially those that involve infringement of the private space of the community members and the collection of health-related information, the ethical burden of breach of privacy and confidentiality of participants emerges as an important issue (31). In the case of passive surveillance based on health facilities, the patients provide implied consent to share their confidential and private health information with the providers for the sake of treatment. This usually does not mean that their data can be accessed for the purpose of maintaining a surveillance database. On the other hand, in the case of active surveillance based in the community, patients may hesitate to provide confidential information to a surveillance officer who is not the care provider. In most surveillance activities, access to identifying information, such as name, address and telephone number, is protected. However, despite this protection, several concerns remain regarding the confidentiality of the data collected. These include (i) to what extent the data is protected; (ii) who gets access to the data; (iii) whether the community knows who gets access; (iv) how long the data will be maintained; and (v) for what purposes the protected data will be used. For example, an implementation research study was carried out in Tanzania on the control of lymphatic filariasis. The study involved the mass administration of drugs and utilised routine surveillance data for research purposes (32). If the use of surveillance data is allowed without adequate ethical oversight, it might constitute an unethical breach of the participant’s privacy, with the participant having no knowledge of how the data will be used. If the community members refuse to voluntarily share data, it will compromise the efficacy of PHS. On the other hand, in order to ensure the efficacy of surveillance, the community members cannot be forced to share their private information. In this context, adequate community buy-in into the PHS activity becomes important. This can be achieved through active community engagement. Though it may not be feasible to obtain the informed consent of each community member to share his/ her data for the purpose of PHS, the lack of consent cannot undermine the need for the community to know about PHS and its potential implications. The principle of solidarity, which reflects what community members are willing to do for the sake of other members of the community, either for the sake of future self-interest or for the sake of genuine altruism, plays an important role in the community’s willingness to share data to promote a strong PHS system (33).

At times, healthcare service data may be used in PHS. With the development of electronic health records, the accessibility of healthcare service data for purposes of PHS has increased. However, this gives rise to several ethical issues. Individual patients might face stigmatisation and other consequences of breach of confidentiality. Patients have the right to know how their health data are being used; this right is violated if the data are accessible to PHS without their explicit consent. Moreover, the PHS having such access to patients’ information may break public trust in the health system. In addition, when there are no regulations to supervise the open sharing of patients’ information, there is a chance of the data being commercially exploited (34). For example, in India, as in many LMICs, there is an active electronic health record of all maternal and child health services delivered through the public health system, known as the Mother and Child Tracking System (35). This system is password-protected and accessible to those who need the information. The data, including identifying information, are accessible to researchers and programme evaluators. There is no system in place for the ethical evaluation of access to this electronic data. Though the Guidelines for Electronic Health Records in India, proposed by the Ministry of Health and Family Welfare, lay down strict regulations for the protection of personal information, a good part of the regulations have yet to be operationalised at the field level (36).

Often, PHS data are analysed and utilised for the specific evaluation of programmes, situation analysis and inferences. In a programme based on the mass administration of drugs for lymphatic filariasis, the routine filarial smear surveillance was analysed to make inferences on the effectiveness of the programme. It is important to remember that surveillance data are neither collected rigorously to ensure the scientific validity required for research, nor are they sampled in a representative manner. Using surveillance data out of context can be an ethical problem since the results are likely to be misleading. The dissemination and sharing of PHS data also pose important ethical dilemmas. In the spirit of solidarity, it may become necessary to share PHS data locally and globally. The International Health Regulations mandate the sharing of PHS data on certain important diseases (37). For public health emergencies of international concern, the IHR recommend global surveillance systems which share data from different countries (38). However, while disseminating and sharing the data, adequate precautions must be taken to prevent breach of confidentiality, with the data being stripped of identifying information. Rather than discussing and debating the ownership of data, ethical discourse should focus on transparency in data sharing, accountability and the justifications for data sharing.

Lastly, setting up appropriate standards of care for patients diagnosed with any of the diseases included in the PHS is an ethical obligation. While setting up PHS, consideration should be given to the strengthening of healthcare delivery for the diseases reported by the people and detected by surveillance. In certain situations, specific disease surveillance is set up with the support of a donor. In these situations, treatment facilities should be established for patients who have been found to have the disease. Further, the PHS system should consider the provision of ancillary care (39). Should care be provided even to those patients diagnosed with diseases that are not covered by the PHS? It may not be possible for the PHS to address all ancillary care responsibilities. However, the strengthening of the overall health system should be able to take care of this.

Ethical oversight for PHS

Whether PHS is research or a public health activity is a contentious issue. Specific guidelines suggest that those activities which collect more data than that required for the delivery of essential services, the findings of which can be generalised to populations other than those that directly participate in the data collection, and which can be used to generate new knowledge are referred to as research. Those activities which collect less data than that required, are applicable to only those from whom the data has been collected, and do not lead to generalisable results are classified as non-research activities (40). If PHS is considered pure research, it would have to be subject to the rigours of research ethics, such as obtaining informed consent and the approval of an independent, impartial ethics committee (18). This may not be feasible in the case of PHS, given that some PHS activities must be undertaken on an urgent basis. On the other hand, if PHS is deemed a non-research activity, it escapes ethical review and is not bound by the other considerations unique to research activities. This may not exactly be a comfortable situation, given the potential ethical burdens involved in PHS. Therefore, some form of ethical oversight is essential for PHS, albeit not a full-fledged review by a research ethics committee. Depending on the individual state’s capacity, this oversight may be provided by regular research ethics committees, or specific public health ethical committees for each public health activity. In LMICs, where the capacity to perform PHS is developing and limited, PHS may take different forms. Sometimes, ad hoc surveillance is established following the outbreak of an illness, such as influenza, for a specific period of time. There may be surveillance of the quality of the air and water immediately after a disaster situation. Such ad hoc PHS activities require a very different form of ethical oversight than does a standard well-established, systematic PHS system. Therefore, the state may not be able to develop a uniform mechanism of ethical oversight for all forms of PHS. Moreover, such ethical oversight may be problematic in LMICs, which have a limited capacity even insofar as regular research ethics committees are concerned. To ensure ethical oversight, there is a need for strong ethical guidance, based both on the main ethical principles and specific ethical issues involved in PHS. It is necessary to build the capacity of public health practitioners, members of ethical committees, policy-makers and other stakeholders to understand the ethical burdens associated with all forms of PHS. A State-level discussion could be initiated to agree upon the most appropriate mechanism of ethical oversight of PHS, and thus institutionalise the ethics of PHS.

Acknowledgments

The author is a member of the WHO working group on the development of ethical guidelines for PHS and has benefited from the discussions of the working group’s meetings.

References

  1. WHO. Public Health Surveillance [Internet], 2016 [cited 2016 Oct 11]. Available from: http://www.who.int/topics/public_health_surveillance/en/
  2. Surveillance [Internet]. National Institute for Communicable Diseases, 2017 [cited 2017 May 30]. Available from: http://www.nicd.ac.za/?page=surveillance&id=88
  3. Brachman PS, Abrutyn E. Bacterial infections of humans: epidemiology and control. Springer; 2009.
  4. Adazu K, Lindblade KA, Rosen DH, Odhiambo F, Ofware P, Kwach J, Van Eijk AM, Decock KM, Amornkul P, Karanja D, Vulule JM, Slutsker L. Health and demographic surveillance in rural western Kenya: a platform for evaluating interventions to reduce morbidity and mortality from infectious diseases. Am J Trop Med Hyg. 2005 Dec;73(6):1151-8.
  5. Herman AA, McCarthy BJ, Bakewell JM, Ward RH, Mueller BA, Maconochie NE, Read AW, Zadka P, Skjaerven R. Data linkage methods used in maternally-linked birth and infant death surveillance data sets from the United States (Georgia, Missouri, Utah and Washington State), Israel, Norway, Scotland and Western Australia. Paediatr Perinat Epidemiol. 1997 Jan;11 Suppl 1:5-22.
  6. Weir HK, Thun MJ, Hankey BF, Ries LA, Howe HL, Wingo PA, Jemal A, Ward E, Anderson RN, Edwards BK. Annual report to the nation on the status of cancer, 1975–2000, featuring the uses of surveillance data for cancer prevention and control. J Natl Cancer Inst. 2003 Sep 3;95(17):1276-99.
  7. Paolotti D, Carnahan A, Colizza V, Eames K, Edmunds J, Gomes G, Koppeschaar C, Rehn M, Smallenburg R, Turbelin C, Van Noort S, Vespignani A. Web-based participatory surveillance of infectious diseases: the Influenzanet participatory surveillance experience. Clin Microbiol Infect. 2014 Jan;20(1):17-21. doi: 10.1111/1469-0691.12477.
  8. Aldis W. Health security as a public health concept: a critical analysis. Health Policy Plan. 2008 Nov [cited 2017 May 30];23(6):369-75. doi: 10.1093/heapol/czn030. Epub 2008 Aug 8. Available from: http://heapol.oxfordjournals.org/content/23/6/369.abstract
  9. Gostin LO, DeBartolo MC, Friedman EA. The International Health Regulations 10 years on: the governing framework for global health security. Lancet. 2015 Nov 28 [cited 2017 May 30];386(10009):2222-6. doi: 10.1016/S0140-6736(15)00948-4. Epub 2015 Nov 25. Available from: http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(15)00948-4
  10. Heymann DL, Chen L, Takemi K, Fidler DP, Tappero JW, Thomas MJ, Kenyon TA, Frieden TR, Yach D, Nishtar S,Kalache A, Olliaro PL, Horby P, Torreele E, Gostin LO, Ndomondo-Sigonda M, Carpenter D, Rushton S, Lillywhite L, Devkota B, Koser K, Yates R, Dhillon RS, Rannan-Eliya RP. Global health security: the wider lessons from the west African Ebola virus disease epidemic. Lancet. 2015 May 9 [cited 2017 May 30];385(9980):1884-901. doi: 10.1016/S0140-6736(15)60858-3. Available from: http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(15)60858-3
  11. Kroll M, Phalkey RK, Kraas F. Challenges to the surveillance of non-communicable diseases – a review of selected approaches. BMC Public Health. 2015 Dec 16 [cited 2017 May 30]; 15:1243. doi: 10.1186/s12889-015-2570-z. Available from: http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4682212/
  12. Hall HI, Correa A, Yoon PW, Braden CR; Centers for Disease Control and Prevention. Lexicon, definitions, and conceptual framework for public health surveillance. MMWR Suppl. 2012 Jul 27;61(3):10-4.
  13. Anand PB, Gasper D, Deneulin S, Townsend N. Public goods, global public goods and the common good. Int J Soc Econ. 2007;34(1/2):19-36.
  14. Childress JF, Faden RR, Gaare RD, Gostin LO, Kahn J, Bonnie RJ, Kass NE, Mastroianni AC, Moreno JD, Nieburg P. Public health ethics: mapping the terrain. J Law Med Ethics. 2002 Summer;30(2):170-8.
  15. Baylis F, Kenny NP, Sherwin S. A relational account of public health ethics. Public Health Ethics 2008;1(3):196-209.
  16. Calain P. Exploring the international arena of global public health surveillance. Health Policy Plan. 2007 Jan [cited 2017 May 30]; 22(1):2-12. Available from: http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/heapol/czl034
  17. Calain P. From the field side of the binoculars: a different view on global public health surveillance. Health Policy Plan. 2007 Jan; 22(1):13-20.
  18. Fairchild AL. Dealing with Humpty Dumpty: Research, Practice, and the Ethics of Public Health Surveillance. J Law Med Ethics. 2003 Winter; 31(4):615-23.
  19. Fairchild AL, Bayer R. Unlinked anonymous testing for HIV in developing countries: a new ethical consensus. Public Health Rep. 2012 Jan-Feb;127(1):115-18.
  20. Tindana PO, Singh JA, Tracy CS, Upshur RE, Daar AS, Singer PA, Frohlich J, Lavery JV. Grand challenges in global health: community engagement in research in developing countries. PLoS Med. 2007 Sep;4(9):e273.
  21. Dickert N, Sugarman J. Ethical goals of community consultation in research. Am J Public Health. 2005 Jul;95(7):1123-7. Epub 2005 Jun 16.
  22. Brinkerhoff DW. Accountability and health systems: toward conceptual clarity and policy relevance. Health Policy Plan. 2004 Nov;19(6):371-9.
  23. Pluye P, Potvin L, Denis J-L. Making public health programs last: conceptualizing sustainability. Eval Program Plann. 2004;27(2):121-33.
  24. Remais J V, Zeng G, Li G, Tian L, Engelgau MM. Convergence of non-communicable and infectious diseases in low- and middle-income countries. Int J Epidemiol. 2013 Feb;42(1):221-7. doi: 10.1093/ije/dys135. Epub 2012 Oct 13.
  25. Alwan A, Maclean DR, Riley LM, d’Espaignet ET, Mathers CD, Stevens GA, Bettcher D. Monitoring and surveillance of chronic non-communicable diseases: progress and capacity in high-burden countries. Lancet. 2010 Nov 27;376(9755):1861-8. doi: 10.1016/S0140-6736(10)61853-3. Epub 2010 Nov 10.
  26. Buse K, Hawkes S. Health in the sustainable development goals: ready for a paradigm shift? Global Health. 2015 Mar 21; 11:13. doi: 10.1186/s12992-015-0098-8.
  27. Hürlimann E, Schur N, Boutsika K, Stensgaard AS, Laserna de Himpsl M, Ziegelbauer K, Laizer N, Camenzind L, Di Pasquale A,Ekpo UF, Simoonga C, Mushinge G, Saarnak CF, Utzinger J, Kristensen TK, Vounatsou P. Toward an open-access global database for mapping, control, and surveillance of neglected tropical diseases. PLoS Negl Trop Dis. 2011 Dec;5(12):e1404. doi: 10.1371/journal.pntd.0001404. Epub 2011 Dec 13.
  28. Liang S, Yang C, Zhong B, Guo J, Li H, Carlton EJ, Freeman MC, Remais JV. Surveillance systems for neglected tropical diseases: global lessons from China’s evolving schistosomiasis reporting systems, 1949–2014. Emerg Themes Epidemiol. 2014 Nov 25 [cited 2017 May 30]; 11:19. doi: 10.1186/1742-7622-11-19. eCollection 2014. Available from: http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4531518/
  29. Thakur J. Integrated disease surveillance–a key step to improve public health in India. Indian J Community Med. 2006;31(4):215.
  30. Rouse WB. Health care as a complex adaptive system: implications for design and management. Bridg Acad Eng. 2008;38(1):17.
  31. Coughlin SS, Beauchamp TL, Weed DL. Ethics and epidemiology. Oxford University Press, New York; 2009.
  32. Simonsen PE, Derua YA, Magesa SM, Pedersen EM, Stensgaard AS, Malecela MN, Kisinza WN. Lymphatic filariasis control in Tanga Region, Tanzania: status after eight rounds of mass drug administration. Parasite Vectors. 2014 Nov 12 [cited 2017 May 30]; 7:507. doi: 10.1186/s13071-014-0507-5. Available from: http://dx.doi.org/10.1186/s13071-014-0507-5
  33. Jennings B. The place of solidarity in public health ethics. Public Health Rev. 2012;34(1):65.
  34. Safran C, Bloomrosen M, Hammond WE, Labkoff S, Markel-Fox S, Tang PC, Detmer DE, Expert Panel. Toward a national framework for the secondary use of health data: an American Medical Informatics Association White Paper. J Am Med Inform Assoc. 2007 Jan-Feb;14(1):1-9. Epub 2006 Oct 31.
  35. Gera R, Muthusamy N, Bahulekar A, Sharma A, Singh P, Sekhar A, Singh V. An in-depth assessment of India’s Mother and Child Tracking System (MCTS) in Rajasthan and Uttar Pradesh. BMC Health Serv Res. 2015 Aug 11 [cited 2017 May 30]; 15:315. doi: 10.1186/s12913-015-0920-2. Available from: http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4530478/
  36. Ozair FF, Jamshed N, Sharma A, Aggarwal P. Ethical issues in electronic health records: a general overview. Perspect Clin Res. 2015 Apr-Jun [cited 2017 May 30]; 6(2):73-6. doi: 10.4103/2229-3485.153997. Available from: http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4394583/
  37. Fidler DP, Gostin LO. The new International Health Regulations: an historic development for international law and public health. J Law Med Ethics. 2006 Spring;34(1):85-94, 4.
  38. Baker MG, Fidler DP. Global public health surveillance under new international health regulations. Emerg Infect Dis. 2006 Jul;12(7):1058-65.
  39. Carrel M, Rennie S. Demographic and health surveillance: longitudinal ethical considerations. Bull World Health Organ. 2008 Aug;86(8):612-6.
  40. CDC. Distinguishing public health research and public health nonresearch policy. Department of Health and Human Services, CDC; 2010 [cited 2017 May 30]. Available from: https://www.cdc.gov/od/science/integrity/docs/cdc-policy-distinguishing-public-health-research-nonresearch.pdf
About the Authors
Vijayaprasad Gopichandran ([email protected])
Assistant Professor, Department of Community Medicine
ESIC Medical College and PGIMSR, KK Nagar, Chennai 600 078, Tamil Nadu, India
Manuscript Editor: Mala Ramanathan
Help IJME keep its content free. You can support us from as little as Rs. 500 Make a Donation