Vol , Issue Date of Publication: January 01, 1998

Views
, PDF Downloads:

COMMENT

Physican, do no harm

Sandhya Srinivasan


Recent publicity about unethical trials raises a number of questions about research in developing countries. It also reminds us of the limitations of accepted safeguards: some of the trials under attack passed ethical review boards in the funding countries and have the approval of the local goverments.

Some months ago, the New England Journal of Medicine carried a comment on 15 on-going clinical trials testing cheaper drug regimens to prevent maternal-foetal transmission of HIV in Africa and Asia. Some 16,000 pregnant, HIV-positive women were enrolled in the placebo-controlled trials. The problem: these trials began after AZT had been found to prevent such transmission by 50% or more, and is recommended to all HIV-positive pregnant women in western countries. In other words, thousands of women in the trials were getting sugar pills to test the efficacy of the new regi mens. If they had been enrolled in trials in the West, they would have received a standard course of AZT.

Nine of the trials are funded by the US Centers for Disease Control or the US National Institutes for Health.

The following points were made, in professional journals and the lay press: Placebo controls in any trial are unacceptable once an effective treatment is found. The research question cannot be: is the drug better than nothing, but is it as good as the other (more expensive) drug. The NEJM argued that earlier trials contained enough data on the shorter regimens being experimented with now, to show that they were better than a placebo.

The argument that placebo controlled trials are more rapid, and need fewer numbers, is unacceptable: researchers cannot put their trial participants at risk for such reasons.

The existent standards of care are the consequence not of medical choices but economic policies which make effective drugs exorbitant. An ethicist working in reproductive health asks, " Why couldn’t the government have taken AZT over as the people’s property, as the French government did with RU486?"

A response from the CDC and the NIH acknowledged the inherent tension between participants’ risks and the public’s benefits, but argued that the logistic problems of administering AZT in Africa, the drug’s toxicity in malnourished women, and the cost, made them look for simpler, cheaper alternatives. And " The most compelling reason to use a placebo-controlled study is that it provides definitive answers to questions about the safety and value of an intervention in the setting in which the study is performed, and these answers are the point of the research." However, logistic problems and cost cannot be reasons for withholding AZT from the control group. Further, the interventions were of known (though lesser) efficacy, according to the NEJM.

A supplement in the Monash Bioethics Review suggests that much research today is poorly formulated, repetitive, and not publicly accounted for. It also attacks the ‘placebo orthodoxy’ in clinical trials, noting the limitations of such trials, and suggesting alternative means. Coincidentally, perhaps, soon after the controversy erupted it was found no longer necessary to use placebo controls.

Much has also been made of the fact that the trials passed ethics boards in funding countries, that they received the women’s informed consent, and that they had the support of the local governments. This is only evidence that such ethics boards are fallible, at best. And governments may, and do, violate their responsibility to people. Even responsible governments may be unable to refuse offers of such trials. Are they really in a position to oppose international funders when the proposal before them offers them a chance to treat a few people, and maybe get a cheap treatment in the long run?

Likewise, individual women who give their ‘informed consent’ in such trials would naturally choose the chance of getting an effective drug, even if they turn out to be the unlucky ones to get a placebo instead; they would never get treatment otherwise. The fact is: ethical issues may sometimes need to be seen in economic terms. The research question was defined not by science but by an essential drug’s cost. Why should any essential drug be beyond the reach of the vast majority of people who need it? Interestingly, governments and international organisations may be willing to bargain for cheap drugs when it comes to contraceptives.

There are some parallels to be drawn between the HIV trials and the ICMR trials on cervical cancer in which 1,158 women with cervical dysplasia were ‘monitored’ to observe the rates of progression to cancer. Investigators say that they did not obtain written consent because most of the women were illiterate. Seventy-one women developed cancer; at least nine developed invasive cancer without treatment. Sixty-two women developed cervical carcinoma in situ before they were treated.

Investigators do not seem to have informed the women that their lesions were known to progress to cancer. Worse, any treatment seems to have been stopped once the study was over. In other words, the women who took part in the study trusting that they would receive better health care than otherwise, were allowed to fend for themselves, even die.

HIV and, to some extent, cervical cancer, is a product of poverty and powerlessness. It could also be argued that in both situations, the health care system is looking for cheaper interventions without challenging the forces that make current interventions so expensive, or inaccessible. Third, did the study examine a new question? Finally, in both cases the women could not have given informed, voluntary consent; they trusted the investigators because they had no other health care.

A 1995 article in the journal Science notes that establishing institutional review boards and obtaining meaningful consent are acknowledged to be two major problems in ensuring ethical human research. This issue will become even more important in the future, as developing countries, particularly those with large burdens of ‘interesting’ diseases, are seen as ideal research settings. For example, HIV infection is so prevalent in a country like Nairobi that a study that would take 15 years in the US can be done in 18 months, and for a lot less.

Especally if you don’t have to use AZT.

References/related reading:

  1. Lurie Peter and Wolfe Sidney: Unethical trials of interventions to reduce perinatal transmission of the Human Immuno-deficiency Virus in developing countries. New England Journal of Medicine 1997; 337: 853-6
  2. Angell Marcia: The ethics of clinical research in the third world. New England Journal of Medicine 1997; 337: 847-9
  3. Varmus Harold, Satcher David: Ethical complexities of conducting research in developing countries. New England Journal of Medicine 1997; 337: 1003-5.
  4. Freedman B, et al: Placebo orthodoxy in clinical research. Part 1: Empirical and methodological myths. Monash Bioethics Review 1997; 16 (October) Special supplement: 12-26.
  5. Stolberg Sheryl Gay: Top US health officials defend third-world HIV research. The New York Times October 2, 1997.
  6. Novak Rachel: Staging ethical AIDS trials in Africa. Science; 1995 269 (8) .
  7. WHO: International ethical guidelines for biomedical research involving human subjects, Geneva: Council for International Organisations of Medical Sciences, 1993.
  8. Mudur Ganapati: Indian study of women with cervical lesions called unethical. British Medical Journal; 1997; 314 (7087)
  9. Jain Meetu: Human guinea pigs. Pioneer. December 6 and 7, 1997.
  10. Jain Meetu: ‘People should not have to pay with their lives for science’. Pioneer. December11, 1997.
  11. Jain Meetu: ICMR admits flouting norms: use of humans as guinea pigs. Pioneer, December 17, 1997
  12. Sachdev Radhika: The ethical dilemmas of a good doctor. The Times of India. December 17, 1997.
About the Authors
Sandhya Srinivasan
Help IJME keep its content free. You can support us from as little as Rs. 500 Make a Donation