Vol VI, Issue 1 Date of Publication: February 16, 2021
DOI: https://doi.org/10.20529/IJME.2020.122

Views
, PDF Downloads:

COVID-19

Emergency use authorisation of Covid-19 vaccines: An ethical conundrum

Vipin M Vashishtha, Puneet Kumar

Published online first on November 26, 2020. DOI:https://doi.org/10.20529/IJME.2020.122

Abstract

Large-scale vaccination with a safe and effective vaccine against Covid-19 is the only way to conquer the ongoing lethal pandemic that has led to extraordinary social and economic upheaval globally. Fortunately, the world is on the verge of developing Covid-19 vaccines in an unprecedentedly short time. More than forty vaccines are in different stages of clinical trials, and a few are in the crucial phase III studies stage. A new demand for emergency use authorisation and rapid deployment of these vaccines before scrutinising phase III trial data is raging in different quarters. Can advancement of the deployment of these vaccines by even a few weeks give us rich public health dividends? Would it be ethical to deploy these novel vaccines based only on the safety and immunogenicity data generated by the phase-I and II clinical trials? Would it be ethical to deny vaccination of vulnerable populations against an untreatable infectious disease despite the availability of reasonably safe and efficacious vaccines for the want of phase III trial data? The answer is not straightforward, as there are many complexities involved. This commentary attempts to discuss some ethical issues involved in a decision to deploy Covid-19 vaccination before phase III trial results are declared.

Keywords: Covid-19, vaccine candidates, bioethics, clinical trials, emergency use

Background

The Severe Acute Respiratory Syndrome Coronavirus type-2 (SARS-CoV-2) pandemic has caused great social and economic upheaval globally. Nearly ten months into the pandemic, hopes of conquering Covid-19 still rest largely on the production of a vaccine. Thanks to the unprecedented speed and scale of development, more than forty candidates are now in advanced stages of clinical trials. Yet whether vaccines will meet our hopes for a return to normal—now, or in the years to come—will depend on our ability to meet a new kind of challenge, one as logistical, operational, and cultural as it is epidemiological, and far more complex than any the world has faced in the history of immunisation to date. Adding further complexity to the existing issues is a new demand for allowing emergency use authorisation of Covid-19 vaccines before completion of the full phase III trials, which poses a new ethical challenge (1). Would it be ethical to deny vaccination to a vulnerable population against an untreatable infectious disease despite the availability of reasonably safe and efficacious vaccines for the want of phase III trial data? Would advancing the deployment of safe and effective vaccine(s) by even a few weeks provide rich public health dividends? This new ethical dilemma has posed a formidable challenge.

Applying the four principles of bioethics

Would it be ethical to deploy the Covid-19 vaccine(s) based on safety and immunogenicity data generated by phase-I and II clinical trials alone, without waiting for the crucial phase-III trials? The answer is not straightforward, as many complexities are involved. The issue needs to be deliberated in detail to see if the four basic principles of bioethics (respect for autonomy, non-maleficence, beneficence, and justice) (2) are satisfied. If any Covid-19 vaccine is deployed without waiting for the phase-III trial data, and vaccination is carried out after obtaining the full informed consent of the vaccinees, there should not be any violation of the principle of respect for autonomy. Non-maleficence (do no harm) is a crucial component of bioethics principles that needs careful deliberation concerning the question. While common adverse effects are less likely to be missed by the phase I/II trials, these trials are underpowered to detect less common adverse effects.

If Covid-19 vaccine is deployed before thoroughly scrutinising phase-III trials, the vaccinees would be subjected to unknown risks. Since a huge population is to be vaccinated, the absolute number of subjects potentially suffering from even less common adverse effects would be significant. Of particular note is the risk of immune enhancement of the disease, that is, the paradoxical risk of more severe disease in individuals who are vaccinated (3). Such an effect has been noted with many vaccine candidates in the past including in-vitro studies of a SARS-CoV-1 vaccine candidate. Very recently, similar concerns have been raised regarding vaccine enhancement of disease about certain SARS-CoV-2 vaccine candidate approaches (4). Thus, we cannot be sure of satisfying the principle of non-maleficence based on our current state of knowledge.

Beneficence and justice are two other principles of bioethics that are to be used as a touchstone to answer the above question. This implies the obligation to produce benefit and provide equal opportunities for everyone, along with fair distribution of benefit to everyone. What benefit the vaccine would provide would vary somewhat with the specific vaccine candidate and its efficacy. The gold standard for any vaccine is to prevent infection (“sterilising immunity”) in all recipients. However, the published animal studies of candidate Covid-19 vaccines, mainly in non-human primates have so far failed to demonstrate that, though a decrease of viral load and protection from severe disease have been shown (5).

It is also known that the risk of moderate to severe disease is highest in elderly patients and those with co-morbidities. However, phase-I and II trials of the vaccine candidates have enrolled only young volunteers without any comorbidity. So, the amount of benefit a vaccine that prevents moderate/severe disease in young, healthy people, where the incidence of the disease is quite low even otherwise, is not difficult to imagine. Furthermore, the safety and immunogenicity data from young and healthy subjects cannot be extrapolated to the elderly population. Alternative vaccine platforms or the addition of adjuvants may be required for adequate immunogenicity in older age groups, as has been the case with influenza vaccines (6).

Further, the durability of the immune response can also not be elucidated from phase I/II trials. The waning of immune responses is known with most human coronavirus infections (5). The common cold coronaviruses like HCoV-229E and HCoV-OC43 are known to provide immunity that lasts from just a few weeks to months (7). These coronavirus infections do not provide lasting protection as challenge experiments suggest, despite having detectable antibodies (8). Re-infections have also been documented with SARS-CoV-2 (9). Thus, unless we have reliable data on the durability of the immune response to the vaccine(s) in question, the degree of beneficence is difficult to ascertain. Even if the Covid-19 vaccine(s) are deployed without undergoing rigorous phase-III trials as has been done in China and Russia (10, 11), these trials would continue to run parallel to deployment to generate scientifically strong data and find answers to unanswered questions.

However, this would add some more ethical issues to the cauldron. Vaccination in the same population where the phase-III trial is going on would affect the trial results. To avoid this, the vaccine would not be offered in the catchment area of the trial. Would this not go against the principle of justice? Would the said population not be deprived of the opportunity to get the vaccine that is licensed?

Is there a precedent?

During the serious epidemic of deadly haemorrhagic fever caused by Ebola virus in 2014, the World Health Organization (WHO) had approved an innovative, open-label phase III, cluster-randomised ring vaccination trial of a candidate Ebola vaccine, rVSV-ZEBOV, produced by Merck & Co. in contacts and contacts of contacts of confirmed cases of Ebola in Guinea (12). Around 2,100 subjects were vaccinated immediately with Merck’s rVSV-ZEBOV, and a similar number of subjects in a control arm received a delayed vaccination 21 days later. No Ebola cases occurred within 10 days or more of treatment in the patients who received immediate vaccination, whereas 23 cases occurred in the control group. The candidate vaccine was found to offer substantial protection against Ebola virus disease with 100% efficacy (13). The innovative “ring design” was chosen for operational, scientific, and ethical reasons, and it was considered ethically superior to individually randomised placebo-controlled trials. However, Covid-19 is not Ebola, which had an exceedingly high mortality (the average mortality of Ebola has been 50%, ranging from 22%-88%) (14). Even the average mortality rate of Ebola virus disease is much higher than mortality observed in the high-risk group with Covid-19 (10-20%) (15).

The pre-phase III efficacy assessment of Covid-19 vaccine candidates hovers around 50-60% which are far below the observed efficacy of Ebola vaccine, rVSV-ZEBOV. Furthermore, there are multiple uncertainties regarding the reliable immune-correlate of protection, duration of immunity, and potentially serious adverse effects like antibody enhanced disease (ADE), a phenomenon already observed with the predecessor of Covid-19 vaccines, the SARS-CoV candidate. Hence, there is a lot of scepticism around the success of Covid-19 vaccines owing to our inadequate knowledge of immunity associated with Covid-19, our past-experience with SARS-CoV-1 vaccines, the absence of sterilising immunity as evident in the non-human primate studies, etc.

Additional complexities

The lack of transparency in many large Covid-19 vaccine trials has already adversely affected the public trust in these vaccines (16). A few large vaccine developers like Moderna, Pfizer, AstraZeneca, and Johnson & Johnson have been forced by the academic community to make public their clinical-trial protocols for vaccine candidates in phase III clinical trials. Concerns about approvals being rushed, fears of political interference, undue pressure on regulatory authorities to approve a vaccine before data show that it is effective and safe, suspicion of the vaccine industry and an outbreak of vaccine misinformation are combining to erode the public’s trust in the vaccine development and approval processes. The primary endpoint of many candidate vaccine trials is “prevention of mild disease” rather than “protection against severe disease and death”.

The growing vaccine hesitancy following a “tsunami” of misinformation and conspiracy theories has the potential to hamper vaccine uptake. The politicisation of Covid-19 vaccination in a few countries has also created suspicion amongst the community. Covid-19 has been an emergency and ethical values vary among countries. Any mishap during pre-emptive Covid-19 vaccination without confirmed approval may have far-reaching negative consequences on overall vaccine confidence and acceptance.

Conclusions

Despite the undoubtedly urgent need for a vaccine to tide over the crisis, it cannot be forgotten that the vaccine needs to be safe and effective to achieve the desired outcome. Deliberately delaying a safe and effective intervention against mounting morbidity and mortality due to the long trial and licensing process may have some ethical consequences. But allowing a potentially unsafe, and “partially tested” intervention offering modest protection to a section of society against a not so lethal illness may be ethically flawed. While innovations like parallel (rather than sequential) phase-I/II trials, studying multiple vaccine candidates in one trial (like the Solidarity vaccine trial proposed by WHO) and starting manufacturing processes in anticipation of licensing, and reducing red tape in the licensing process might be considered as means to fast track vaccine development and deployment; skipping crucial phase-III trials does not seem to pass the test of ethical scrutiny. While options offering light at the end of the tunnel are welcome, we should tread very carefully with this new virus and not be blinded by the light: everything that glitters is not gold!!

Conflicts of interest and funding: None declared

References

  1. Krause PR, Gruber MF. Emergency use authorization of Covid vaccines – safety and efficacy follow-up considerations. N Engl J Med. 2020 Oct 16. Doi: 10.1056/NEJMp2031373.
  2. Beauchamp T, Childress J. Principles of Biomedical Ethics. 7th edition. New York: Oxford University Press; 2013.
  3. Takada A, Kawaoka Y. Antibody-dependent enhancement of viral infection: molecular mechanisms and in vivo implications. Rev Med Virol. 2003 Nov-Dec;13(6):387‐98. Doi: 10.1002/rmv.405.
  4. Grifoni A, Weiskopf D, Ramirez SI, Mateus J, Dan JM, Rydyznski-Moderbacher C,et al. Targets of T cell responses to SARS-CoV-2 coronavirus in humans with COVID-19 disease and unexposed individuals. Cell. 2020 Jun 25; 181 (7): 1489-1501. e15. Doi: 10.1016/j.cell.2020.05.015.
  5. Vashishtha VM, Kumar P. Development of SARS-CoV2 vaccines: Challenges, risks and the way forward. Hum Vaccin Immunother. 2020 (In press). ID: 1845524 Doi:10.1080/21645515.2020.1845524)
  6. Wagner A, Weinberger B. Vaccines to prevent infectious diseases in the older population: Immunological challenges and future perspectives. Front Immunol. 2020 Apr 23;11: 717. Doi: 10.3389/fimmu.2020.00717.
  7. Regalado A. What if immunity to Covid19 doesn’t last? MIT Technology Review. 2020 Apr 27[cited 2020 Nov 1]. Available from: https://www.technologyreview.com/2020/04/27/1000569/how-long-are-people-immune-to-covid-19/.
  8. Callow KA, Parry HF, Sergeant M, Tyrrell DA. The time course of the immune response to experimental coronavirus infection of man. Epidemiol Infect. 1990 Oct;105(2):435–46. Doi: 10.1017/s0950268800048019.
  9. Iwasaki A. What reinfections mean for COVID-19. Lancet Infect Dis. 2020 Oct 12. Corrected Nov 6 [cited 2020 Nov 17]. Available from: https://doi.org/10.1016/S1473-3099(20)30783-0.
  10. Reuters Staff. CanSino’s COVID-19 vaccine candidate approved for military use in China. Reuters.com. 2020 Jun 29[cited 2020 Oct 31]. Available from: https://www.reuters.com/article/us-health-coronavirus-china-vaccine-idUSKBN2400DZ.
  11. Callaway E. Russia’s fast-track coronavirus vaccine draws outrage over safety. Nature. 2020 Aug; 584(7821): 334-5. Doi: 10.1038/d41586-020-02386-2.
  12. World Health Organization. Update with the development of Ebola vaccines and implications of emerging evidence to inform future policy recommendations. [cited 2020 Nov 20] Available from: https://www.who.int/immunization/sage/meetings/2017/april/1_Ebola_vaccine_background_document.pdf
  13. Henao-Restrepo AM, Camacho A, Longini IM, Watson CH, Edmunds WJ, Egger M, et al. Efficacy and effectiveness of an rVSV-vectored vaccine in preventing Ebola virus disease: final results from the Guinea ring vaccination, open-label, cluster-randomised trial (Ebola Ça Suffit!). Lancet. 2017 Feb 4; 389(10068):505-18. Doi: 10.1016/SO140-6736(16)32621-6.
  14. World Health Organization. Ebola virus disease. Geneva: WHO; 2020 Feb 10[cited 2020 Nov 3]. Available from: https://www.who.int/news-room/fact-sheets/detail/ebola-virus-disease
  15. Our World in Data. Mortality Risk of Covid-19. [cited 2020 Nov 20] Available from: https://ourworldindata.org/mortality-risk-covid.
  16. Editorial. COVID vaccine confidence requires radical transparency. Nature. 2020 Oct; 586(7827):8. Doi: 10.1038/d41586-020-02738-y.
About the Authors
Vipin M Vashishtha ([email protected])
Director and Consultant Paediatrician, Department of Paediatrics, Mangla Hospital and Research Centre, Shakti Chowk,
Bijnor 246 701 Uttar Pradesh INDIA
Clinician, Kumar Child Clinic, KM Chowk, Sector 12,
Dwarka, New Delhi, INDIA.
Help IJME keep its content free. You can support us from as little as Rs. 500 Make a Donation